Where Shall Wisdom Be Found?
Harold Bloom
Riverhead Books, New York, New York (USA), 2004 (2004)
284 pages
|
It is not easy for a literary critic to become well known beyond the world
of academia these days (was it ever easy though?), but Harold Bloom definitely has achieved a
significant degree of recognition for someone who, after all, just writes
about books. He has written essays about Percy Shelley, Blake, Yeats, the Kabbalah, Gnosticism, and
a myriad other issues. However, it was The Western Canon that
without any doubt catapulted him to international fame. Published in 1994,
right in the middle of the offensive of the politically correct movement, Bloom clearly
asserts the need for a literary canon that helps us distinguish between the
good and the mediocre, and since his particular canon is dominated by
what other people might prefer to call dead white men, Bloom ran into
a considerable opposition in some quarters that accused him of
ultraconservatism. I simply do not see the connection between his firm
belief in a canon and any form of ultraconservative ideology, but since
we are not discussing The Western Canon here I suppose we should leave
that discussion for another day. Suffice to say though that one will find
enough quotes in this book to clarify Bloom's opinions of today's palladins
of deconstruction:
As the editor of the four-volume Supplement to the Oxford English
Dictionary (final volume published in 1986), Burchfield gave nearly
thirty years to his Johnsonian task, and emerged from it with a Johnsonian
literary humanism enhanced. He is a historical philologist, which is to be
a dissident in an era dominated by descriptive linguistics. A critic
who takes (as I do) a historical view of rhetoric, as opposed to the
theory of Paul de Man,
is bound to be attracted by Burchfield's principles. What vanishes in
deconstructive criticism is the pragmatic distinction between denotation,
or naming, and connotation, or association, upon which poetry depends.
Saussure sets a bar between signifier and signified, but then cannot tell
us on which side of the bar connotation is to be discovered. Without a
sense of connotation, the reader would be tone-deaf, and all figurative
language would become a form of irony, as it does in de Man's formulations.
(pp. 160-161)
In any case, whatever one thinks about Bloom and his ideas, there is little
doubt he prizes consistency and has spent quite a few years now telling his
story and defending his views. Back in 2000, Bloom published How to Read
and Why, whose preface starts with the following lines:
There is no single way to read well, though there is a prime reason why we
should read. Information is endlessly available to us; where shall wisdom
be found? If you are fortunate, you encounter a particular teacher who
can help, yet finally you are alone, going on without further mediation.
Reading well is one of the great pleasures that solitude can afford you,
because it is, at least in my experience, the most healing of pleasures. It
returns you to otherness, whether in yourself or in friends, or in those who
may become friends. Imaginative literature is otherness, and as such
alleviate loneliness. We read not only because we cannot know enough people,
but because friendship is so vulnerable, so likely to diminish or disappear,
overcome by space, time, imperfect sympathies, and all the sorrows of familial
and passional life.
(p. 19)
Apparently, it took him four more years to go back to those words and write
about where is it that we can find wisdom in the books, but not without first
having a near brush with death that made him return to life with a renewed
sense of urgency. This is the consequence of that rush to study again some
of the greatest thinkers and writers of the Western world in search of
meaning. As he clarifies in the first page:
All of the world's cultures —Asian, African, Middle Eastern,
European/Western Hemisphere— have fostered wisdom writing. For more
than a half-century I have studied and taught the literature that emerged
from monotheism and its later secularizations. Where Shall Wisdom Be
Found? rises out of personal need, reflecting a quest for sagacity that
might solace and clarify the traumas of aging, recovery from grave illness,
and of grief for the loss of beloved friends.
(p. 1)
The impressive list of authors and works that Blooms writes about in this
book includes The Book of Job, Ecclesiastes, Plato, Homer,
Cervantes, Shakespeare, Montaigne, Francis Bacon, Samuel Johnson, Goethe,
Emerson, Nietzche, Freud, Proust, The Gospel of Thomas and St.
Augustine.
Distinction between wisdom literature and philosophy:
If Falstaff and Hamlet, Iago and Cleopatra, Lear and Macbeth are only roles
for performances, then what are we? Wisdom is there to be found, in Job and
Koheleth, in the Gospel of Mark and the Gospel of Thomas, in Cervantes and
in Shakespeare. If your quest is for wisdom within the bounds of reason,
rather than of wonder, then go back to Plato and his progeny, down through
David Hume to Wittgenstein. Plato, I think, would have approved the
reservations concerning Shakespeare expressed by Hume and by Wittgenstein.
But even a long life is too short to receive everything Shakespeare is
capable of giving you.
(p. 57)
On the Book of Job:
The translator Stephen Mitchell, in his interesting version of Job (1986),
poignantly remarks that Job truly loves God without ever expecting Him
to love us in return, a ver un-American sentiment, since the Gallup poll
every second year tells us that eighty-nine-percent of Americans believe
that God loves them on a personal and individual basis. The American God,
like the American Jesus, is surprisingly nonbiblical, but then Americans
are not very Jobean.
(p. 21)
On Homer:
The poet of the Iliad seems to me to have only one ancient rival,
the prime and original author of much of Genesis, Exodus, Numbers, known as
the Yahwist or J writer to scholars. Homer and J have absolutely nothing
in common except their uncanny sublimity, and they are sublime in very
different modes. In a profound sense, they are antagonists, though
neither ever heard of the other, or listened to the other's texts. They
compete for consciousness of Western nations, and their belated strife may
be the largest single factor that makes for a divided sensibility in the
literature and life of the West. For what marks the West is its troubled
sense that its cognition goes one way and it spiritual life goes in quite
another. We have no ways of thinking that are not Greek, and yet our
morality and religion —outer and inner— find their ultimate source
in the Hebrew Bible.
(p. 68)
It can be argued that the speactatorship of the gods gives Homer an
immense aesthetic advantage over the writers of the Hebrew Bible. The
sense of a divine audience constantly in attendance both provides a
fascinating interplay with Homer's human auditors and guarantees that
Achilles and Hector will perform in front of a sublimity greater even than
their own. To have the gods as one's audience enhances and honors the
heroes who are Homer's prime actors. Yahweh frequently hides Himself,
and will not be there when you cry out for Him, or He may call out your
name unexpectedly, to which you can only respond, "Here I am". Zeus is
capricious and is finally limited by fate. Yahweh surprises you, and has
no limitation. He will not lend you dignity by serving as your audience,
and yet He is anything but indifferent to you. He fashioned you out
of the moistened red clay, and then blew his own breath into your nostrils,
so as to make you a living being. You grieve Him or you please Him, but
fundamentally He is your longing for the father, as Freud insisted. Zeus
is not your longing for anyone, and he will not save you even if you are
Heracles, his own son.
(pp. 73-74)
On Homer and Plato:
Together, Homer and Plato are so strong that their only rival before
Dante, Cervantes and Shakespeare is the Yahwist, who composed the earliest
and most crucial stratum of Torah (in Genesis, Exodus, Numbers, with many
later insertions by the Redactor, in the Babilonian exile) sometime between
980 and 900 B.C.E., before Homer lived and died. The ultimate agon has to be
that between the Yahwist's Moses, enigmatic hero of the Torah, and Socrates,
captured forever by Plato, despite hte genius of Aristophanes in his great
farce The Clouds (424 B.C.E.), and the devoted candor of the pragmatic
Xenophon, heroic chronicler of Anabasis, or The Persian
Expedition, in which Xenophon leads an army of Greek freebooters, and
marches them back to safety after their patron, Cyrus the Younger, is killed
in battle by the forces of his enemy brother, the Persian king.
(p. 32)
Plato, better than any now alive, perceived the aesthetic supremacy of
Homer, but regarded Socrates as the truer guide to wisdom both moral and
religious. Whether the epic tragedy of Achilles and the epic comedy of
Odysseus possess less truth than the discourses of Plato's Socrates is a
highly disputable contention, yet I am alogos, averse to philosophy,
since first I fell in love with the poetry of William Blake and Hart Crane.
I do not read Hume and Wittgenstein except as a searcher for arresting
aphorisms, and I turn incessantly back to Shakespeare in quest for truth,
power, beauty, and for persons, above all else.
(pp. 35-36)
Our civilization is still split between a Hellenic cognition and
aesthetic and a Hebraic morality and religion. One might say that the
hand of Western (indeed of much Eastern also) civilization has five
ill-assorted fiingers: Moses, Socrates, Jesus, Shakespeare, Freud.
Plato's culture is entirely Socratic, by design, yet also Homeric,
unwillingly. Between the Republic and ourselves come Moses, Jesus,
Shakespeare, Freud, and though we cannot abandon Athens, still less could
we avoid our tongues' cleaving to the roofs of our mouths if we do not
prefer Jerusalem to Athens.
(pp. 36-37)
Manifestly, the attack on Homer will not satisfy any reader who rightly
values the Iliad as one of the crowns of imaginative literature,
and yet the issue of wisdom here is religious, though certainly not in any
Hebraic sense. Plato's Socrates wants the gods to be devoid of
personality: free of lust, envy, and everything else that interests us in
Homer's Zeus, much of the time. Like the Christian Platonists who
were to follow him, the divine Plato is obsessed with salvation, hardly a
Homeric notion. Unlike the biblical Hebrews, who had no theology, Plato
most certainly did, though it is difficult to summarize. Something in
me does not altogether ascribe Plato's resentment of Homer to the
philosopher's spirituality, but doubtless it intensified Plato's agon with
the teacher of all Hellas.
(pp. 42-43)
Let us set aside the Timaeus and the Laws. Will the common
reader, now as always, absorb more wisdom from the Republic and the
Symposium than from the Iliad and the Odyssey? Do Hume
and Wittgenstein make us wiser than Hamlet and King Lear? In
search of wisdom, ought I to reread (most reluctantly) Foucault on power and
sadomasochism, or Proust's In Search of Lost Time? The questions
are absurd: competing with Homer, Shakespeare, and Proust is hopeless unless
you are Aeschylus, Cervantes, and Joyce. Plato is unique among philosophers
because, as Emerson said, "he has clapped copyright upon the world". Yet
Homer is the world, and could not be coyprighted.
(p. 54)
On Cervantes and Shakespeare:
Mark Van Doren, in a very useful study, Don Quixote's Profession, is
haunted by the analogues between the Knight and Hamlet, which to me seem
inevitable. Here are the two characters, beyond all others, who seem
always to know what they are doing, though they baffle us whenever we try
to share their knowledge. It is a knowledge unlike that of Sir John Falstaff
and Sancho Panza, who are so delighted at being themselves that they bid
knowledge to go aside and pass them by. I would rather be Falstaff or
Sancho than a version of Hamlet or Don Quixote, because growing old and ill
teaches me that being matters more than knowing. The Knight and Hamlet are
reckless beyond belief; Falstaff and Sancho have some awareness of discretion
in matters of valor.
(pp. 97-98)
Goethe remarked of Shakespeare that each of his plays "revolves around an
invisible point which no philosopher has discovered or defined and where the
characteristic quality of our being, our presumed free will, collides with
the inevitable course of the whole". Later, in his ultimate tribute,
"No End to Shakespeare", Goethe distinguishes between ancient and modern
literature. In ancient literature, the conflict is between moral obligation
and its fulfillment, while in modern literature the agon is between desire
and fulfillment. In Goethe's judgment, Shakespeare is unique in that
he fuses ancient and modern with surpassing exuberance: "In his plays,
obligation and desire clearly try to counterbalance each other".
(p. 113)
On Montaigne:
The personal essay is Montaigne's, as the drama is Shakespeare's, the
epic is Homer's, and the novel forever Cervantes's. That the first of
essayists remains much the best has less to do with his formal originality
(though that is considerable) than with the overwhelming directness of his
wisdom. He asks us implictly and incessantly: Are your thoughts of any
value if they stay within you? His answer, in clear anticipation of
Nietzsche, is no. Thoughts are events. Montaigne's pleasures for the
reader are ultimately difficult, but immediately available, like
Shakespeare's. He asks you to be a vigorous reader, and his modesty is a
mask.
(p. 119)
The wisdom of Montaigne, as we saw earlier in this chapter, has everything
to do with how we ought to live: self-knowledge leads to self-acceptance,
accurate self-expectations, and goodness toward the self and others.
There, I essentially followed Donald Frame, Montaigne's definitive
translator.
(p. 148)
On Goethe:
There is rather little in common between Ecclesiastes, a somber and fierce
vision of reality, and Goethe's serene contemplations of our condition.
Montaigne's full acceptance of the common life differs in temper from Goethe's
ideal of Bildung, the self-development of the elite individual.
Bildung, once a prime educational motive both on the Continent and
in the America of Emerson, seems now to be an obsolete project. Its last
major literary proponent was Goethe's disciple Thomas Mann, whose The
Magic Mountain charted the ironic Bildung of Hans Castorp, caught
between two opposed mentors, the Italian liberal Humanist Settembrini, and
the Jesuit Jewish Naphta, permanently reactionary. Mann ironically keeps
stressing how ordinary Castorp is, but the youthful hero of The Magic
Mountain would be remarkable in any group at any time.
(pp. 176-177)
Goethe is one of the best antidotes I know for our current ideologies of
Resentment, which have now pretty well destroyed aesthetic education in the
English-speaking world. I am not suggesting a reununciatory criticism
to match his poetics of renunciation. The disturbances of 1967-1970 were
not exactly on the scale of the French Revolution, and yet they have made a
culture of Bildung impossible. Goethe does not find me
as Dr. Johnson does, and yet both of them are wisdom teachers for the current
age. The Christian Johnson and the pagan Goethe come together in their
appreciation of Shakespeare, who wrote neither the poetry of desire nor the
poetry of renunciation. Call Shakespeare's the poetry of all climes and
climates, and of all seasons of the soul.
(p. 189)
On Nietzsche:
An admirable study by Alexander Nehamas, Niezsche: Life as Literature
(1983), argues that Friedrich Nietzsche views life as a literary text,
human beings as literary characters, and knowledge as literary criticism.
Were Nehamas preciely right, then Nietzsche could not be judged to be a
wisdom writer, akin to Emerson. Clearly, as Nehamas intimates, Nietzsche
understood his limitations, and made his work available to be interpreted
other than philosophically. Wisdom writers are rarely philosophers:
Montaigne and Bacon, Johnson and Goethe, Emerson and Nietzsche, Freud and
Proust, are not Descartes and Hobbes, Spinoza and Leibniz, Hume and Kant,
Hegel and Wittgenstein. The ancient quarrel between poetry and philosophy
can never end, and wisdom writing is more poetic than philosophical.
(p. 208)
To give suffering a meaning is not so much to relieve suffering as it is to
enable meaning to get started, rather than merely repeated. What Nietzsche
shares more deeply with the Hebrew Bible and with Freud is the drive to find
sense in everything, to interpret everything, but here Nietzsche is at his
most dialectical, since he knows (and cannot accept) the consequences of
everything having a meaning. There could never be anything new, since
everything would have happened already; that is the Hebrew Bible's
loyalty to Yahweh, its trust in the Covenant, and finally that is Freud's
faith in the efficacy of interpretation. And that is Nietzsche's most
profound argument with the Hebrew Bible.
(p. 215)
What the poet means is hurtful, Nietzsche tells us, nor can we tell the
hurt from the meaning. What are the pragmatic consequences for wisdom of
Nietzsche's poetcis of pain? To ask that is to ask also what I am convinced
is the determining question of the canonical: what makes one poem more
memorable than another? The Nietzschean answer must be that the memorable
poem, the poem that has more meaning, or starts more meaning going, is the
poem that gives (or commemorates) more pain.
(p. 219)
On Freud:
In search of wisdom literature in the twentieth century, I initially found it
odd that the two figures who seemed to me incontrovertible should have been
the founder of psychoanalysis and the major novelist of the age. Sigmund
Freud insisted that he had developed a science that would make a vital
contribution to biology, but in that regard he was self-deceived. He became
not the Darwin but the Montaigne of his era, a superb moral essayist rather
than a revolutionist who overturned our sense of humankind's place in
nature. Marcel Proust disputes with James Joyce the eminence of the
greatest literary artist of their age, yet Proust is the wisest of
story-tellers, while Joyce's project was to alter and complete Western
literary tradition, and wisdom was secondary to other concern in Joyce's
writing.
(p. 221)
Our inability to characterize Freud without revising him is a true sign of
his varied strength. His central ideas —the drives, the defenses,
the psychic agencies, the dynamic unconscious— are all frontier
concepts, making ghostlier the demarcations between mind and body. Freud's
science, psychoanalysis, is neither primarily speculative/poetic nor
empirical/therapeutic but is on the border between all prior disciplines.
So his concept of negation is a frontier idea also, breaking down the
distinction between inwardness and outwardness. In Freudian negation, as in
normative Jewish memory, a previously repressed thought, desire, or feeling
achieves formulation only by being disowned, so that it is cognitively
accepted but still effectively denied. Thinking is freed from its sexual
past, even as thinking is desexualized also in the rituals of normative
Judaism.
(p. 228)
On the Gospel of Thomas:
The popularity of the Gospel of Thomas among Americans is another indication
that, as I have argued elsewhere, there is indeed "the American religion":
creedless, Orphic, enthusiastic, protognostic, post-Christian. Unlike the
canonical gospels, that of Judas Thomas the Twin spares us the Crucifixion,
makes the Resurrection unnecessary, and does not present us with a God named
Jesus. No dogmas could be founded uppon this sequence (if it is a
sequence) of apothegms. If you turn to the Gospel of Thomas, you encounter
a Jesus who is unsponsored and free. No one could be burned or even scorned
in the name of this Jesus, and no one has been hurt in any way, except perhaps
for those bigots, high church or low, who may have glanced at so permanently
surprising a work. (...) The Jesus of the Gospel of Thomas calls us to
knowledge and not to belief, for faith need not lead to wisdom; and this
Jesus is a wisdom teacher, gnomic and wandering, rather than a proclaimer of
finalities. You cannot be a minister of this gospel, nor found a church
upon it. The Jesus who urges his followers to be passersby is a remarkably
Whitmanian Jesus, and there is little in the Gospel of Thomas that would not
have been accepted by Emerson, Thoreau, and Whitman.
(pp. 259-260)
On Saint Augustine:
Aside from his vast contributions to theology, Augustine invented reading
as we have known it for sixteen centuries. I am not unique in my elegiac
sadness at watching reading die, in the era that celebrates Stephen King
and J. K. Rowling rather than Charles Dickens and Lewis Carroll. Augustine
was essentially the first theorist and defender of reading, though as an
ethical interpreter he would have repudiated a stance like my own, which
seeks a secular wisdom fused with a purely aesthetic experience at once
freely hedonistic and cognitively strong. (...) We think because we
learn to remember our reading the best that can be read —for Augustine
the Bible and Vergil, Cicero and the Neoplatonists, to which we have added
for ourselves Plato, Dante, Cervantes, and Shakespeare, with Jouce and
Proust in the century just past. But always we remain the progeny of
Augustine, who first told us that the book alone could nourish thought,
memory, and their intricate interplay in the life of the mind. Reading
alone will not save us or make us wise, but without it we will lapse into
the death-in-life of the dumbing down in which America now leads the world,
as in all other matters.
(pp. 277-278)
Final words:
A Jobean wisdom is scarcely American; our national epics are
Moby-Dick, which defies Job's God, and Whitman's Leaves of
Grass, an inextricable mingling of hope an torment. Neither work is
Christian. Is the wisdom of the Greeks and Hebrews, or of the great
moral essayists, still as available to us as is the dark comedy of
Cervantes or the sublimity of Shakesperean tragedy? This book has summoned
these up, in conjunction with the enigmas of a Jesus varied enough to
encompass the Gospel of Thomas, Saint Augustine, and Kierkegaard's indirect
communication of the difficulty of becoming a Christian in a supposedly
Christian society that actually worships Nemesis despite arguing for hope.
As Davide Stimilli suggests, Nemesis is not a moral power: she is the goddess
of retribution, Homeric and Freudian, and not Christian or Platonic. Goethe
and Emerson, themselves not Christian, try to teach us that there is a god
in us who can, for a time anyway, hold out against Nemesis. Pragmatically,
that became William James's benign insight that wisdom had to become a
capacity to overlook what cannot be surmounted. Is that our only answer
now to the query of where shall wisdom be found? At least it does
constitute a difference that helps get us through the hard or unlucky
days.
I personally hope that wisdom literature, as surveyed in this book, can
offer us more than that. Western monotheism —Judaic, Christian,
Islamic&mdhas; is perhaps not so much opposed as it is complemented by the
reliance of Goethe, Emerson, and Freud on individual genius, or daemonic
Eros. Secular wisdom tradition and monotheistic hope may not finally be
reconcilable, at least not wholly, but the greatest of writers ancient and
modern —Homer, Dante, Cervantes, Shakespeare— contrive balances
(however precarious) that allow prudential wisdom and some intimations of
hope to coexist. We read and reflect because we hunger and thirst after
wisdom. Truth, according to the poet William Butler Yeats, could not
be known but could be embodied. Of wisdom, I personally would affirm the
reverse: We cannot embody it, yet we can be taught how to know wisdom,
whether or not it can be identified with the Truth that might make us free.
(pp. 283-284)
Entrevista
con Harold Bloom
Entertainment factor: 4/10
Intellectual factor: 6/10
|